We've got a 2-valued logic, a very nice 3-valued logic called #RM3, and "A useful four-valued logic", N. D. Belnap, 1977. The obvious question is, what about \(n\)-valued logics, for \( n \ge 5 \)? Sadly, the very nice structures we've seen don't generalize. This is often the case, as when we go from the reals to the complex numbers we lose ordering, and when we go to the quaternions we lose commutativity. So it is with this family of logics. Going from 3 to 4 values breaks ordering, but enough structure remains to have something workable (and non-monotonic logics are definitely a thing). Beyond 4 though, we lose more important structure. In Kalman, J. A. (1958) "Lattices with involution," Kalman (no, not Kálmán), showed that these three, plus the trivial lattice \( D_1 \), are the only distributive lattices with involution, the involution being the negation \( \lnot \lnot A = A \). Any larger \( D_n \) decomposes into the smaller ones. Any element of a lattice that satisfies \( \lnot x=x \) is called a 'zero', and Kalman showed that for this setup, there can be only 0, 1, or 2 zeros, corresponding to the 3 lattices shown in the figure.
Furthermore there is a simple proof in Busaniche and Cignoli (2011), "Remarks on an algebraic semantics for paraconsistent Nelson’s logic," that #RM3, the \( D_3 \) lattice with involution, is *unique*.
It is still possible to construct logics with more than 4 (even infinite) truth values, but you lose monotonicity, or other nice properties. #RM3 obeys the law of small numbers; its unique structure follows from it being the *smallest*. The monoid multiplication in \( \mathbb F_4 \) contains the smallest symmetric group \( S_3 \) on 3 elements, aka the Bellman's Rule